Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-jr42d Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-20T08:30:25.650Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Psychiatrist in Search of a Science

II. Developments in the Logic and the Sociology of Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  29 January 2018

Elliot Slater*
Affiliation:
Institute of Psychiatry, De Crespigny Park, London, SE5 8AF

Extract

If, at this distance in time, neither Mapother's nominalism nor Golla's vitalism-holism are at all satisfying, this is because so much has happened to the philosophy of science in the interval. The writings of Sir Karl Popper have had a revolutionary influence; and the important work he has done over thirty years or so is readily available in The Logic of Scientific Discovery (LSD, 1968) and Conjectures and Refutations (CR, 1969). Popper starts from the position that no logical basis for the accumulation of knowledge can be laid on inductive processes (and he also maintains that this is not the way the mind of the scientist works). From observing crows, and seeing that one after another they are all black, one cannot conclude that all crows are black. In general terms, it is not possible to proceed logically from single existential (‘there are …’) statements to universal statements; and an epistemological process that based itself on induction would be rocky at its very foundations. How is it then that science progresses, making mistakes from time to time, but recovering from them, providing for itself a firmer foundation for further work, anchoring it more deeply and extending it more widely? This could only be if the basic logical processes were not, in fact, inductive, as the nineteenth century scientist supposed. The search for an acceptable basic principle came down to finding a criterion of demarcation which would distinguish the empirical sciences from other branches of learning. Popper found it in the principle of refutability.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Royal College of Psychiatrists, 1973 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bressler, Marvin (1968). ‘Sociology, biology and ideology’, in Biology and Behavior: Genetics (ed. Glass, David C.). New York (The Rockefeller University Press and Russell Sage Foundation), 178210.Google Scholar
Harré, R. (1970). The Principles of Scientific Thinking. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. (1970, first published 1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago and London: University of Chicago.Google Scholar
Lakatos, Imre (1970). ‘Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes’, in Lakatos, and Musgrave, , q.v., 91196.Google Scholar
Lakatos, Imre and Musgrave, Alan (Ed.) (1970). Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: University Press.Google Scholar
Mayr, Ernst (1972). ‘The nature of the Darwinian revolution.’ Science, 176, 981–9.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl (1968, first published 1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl (1969, first published 1963). Conjectures and Refutations, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand (1954, first published 1918). Mysticism and Logic. Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Williams, L. Pearce (1970). ‘Normal science, scientific revolutions and the history of science’, in Lakatos, and Musgrave, , q.v., 4950.Google Scholar
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.