Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-hgkh8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-28T03:20:59.727Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Psychosomatic pain

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

Stephen Tyrer*
Affiliation:
Department of Psychiatry, University of Newcastle upon Tyne, Leazes Wing, Royal Victoria Infirmary, Newcastle upon Tyne NE1 4LP, UK. E-mail: s.p.tyrer@ncl.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Columns
Copyright
Copyright © 2006 The Royal College of Psychiatrists 

As a psychiatrist working in the field of pain, it is commonly assumed that I devote most of my attention to people who have pain as a result of stress or psychological difficulties. Indeed, 24 years ago when I first started seeing individuals in chronic pain who had been referred to me in a pain clinic because it was thought that organic factors were insufficient to explain the complaint of pain, I looked carefully for psychiatric and psychological explanations. Despite the fact that one-third of people attending our clinic had evidence of psychiatric illness (Reference Tyrer, Capon and PetersonTyrer et al, 1989), it has become clear to me from those I see that such psychiatric morbidity is largely a result of chronic pain and is not a forerunner of a painful state. The vast majority of people I see in a multidisciplinary pain clinic have a clear organic cause for pain either in the present or past, and it is rare to have a patient with pain arising purely from emotional causes. There is evidence of environmental and social factors affecting the exhibition of pain. Psychiatric illness is more common in people with pain referred to psychiatric out-patient clinics (Reference MerskeyMerskey, 1965; Reference Merskey, Lau and RussellMerskey et al, 1987), but in total the evidence for organic factors leading to distress in vulnerable individuals is overwhelming.

A sizeable number of people in distress from chronic pain do not have enough signs of illness to persuade doctors that organic factors are sufficient to explain their symptoms. These individuals usually show intense conviction of disease, strong adherence to mechanistic explanations of their illness and considerable functional disability arising from the painful complaint. They are undoubtedly in distress and they score highly on symptoms of depression and, to a lesser extent, other psychiatric illnesses. Why these people present in the way they do cannot be deduced solely through application of the medical model.

PAIN AND MIND-BODY DUALISM

The word pain comes from the Latin poena, which means punishment or penalty, after the Roman goddess of punishment. The term was originally used for the punishment of an offence against the law. Over time the word was increasingly used to denote suffering, particularly if this had resulted from a blameworthy act.

Early writers equated emotional suffering with pain and the words were used interchangeably. This psychological dimension to the experience of pain was largely forgotten following Descartes' observations illustrating pain as a signal of physical pathology:

‘quand je ressens de la douleur au pied, la physique m'apprend que ce sentiment se communique par le moyen des nerfs dispersés dans le pied, le pied, qui se trouvant tendus comme des cordes depuis là jusqu'au cerveau, lorsqu'ils sont tiré dans le pied, tirent aussi en même temps l'endroitdu cerveau d'ou ils viennent et auquel ils aboutissent, et y excitent un certain mouvementque la nature a institué pour faire sentir de la douleur à l'esprit, comme si cette douleur était dans le pied’ (Reference DescartesDescartes, 1647).

Although not anatomically precise this work convinced scientists of the relationship between the integrity of sensory nerve conduction and the experience of pain. The experimental work then conducted supported the views of doctors that pain was due to tissue damage, so in those complaining of pain there must be a source of injury. The concept of non-organic pain was not considered important at this time. It was not until Breuer & Freud (edition Reference Breuer, Freud and Strachey1957), in detailed case histories originally published in their studies on hysteria in 1895, suggested that pain could be a manifestation of a psychological problem, that the contribution of psychological factors to pain was reconsidered. The profound influence of Freud shaped the belief in psychological and psychiatric circles that persistent pain associated with emotional distress in the absence of organic findings is primarily due to a psychiatric illness. This was not generally acknowledged by physicians although a number of pain specialists have realised the importance of psychosocial factors in the presentation of patients with chronic pain (Reference Fields, Price and GuttenplanFields & Price, 1994; Reference LivingstonLivingston, 1998). Dr Livingston, a surgeon writing in the middle of the past century, disagreed with the concept supported by many doctors at the time that pain, without physical findings, is hysterical or due to malingering.

PSYCHIATRISTS AND PAIN

The concept of ‘emotional pain’ occupied a select group of British psychiatrists in the 1960s and Erwin Stengel proposed a variety of mechanisms to explain this phenomenon. Stengel was born in Vienna as an identical twin and came to England in 1938 following the occupation of Austria by Hitler. He was intrigued by those who seem to be impervious to pain and described case studies of this phenomenon. More than most, he understood that mechanistic models were inadequate to explain the gamut of experiences described by people with pain. The controversy between Stengel and Eliot Slater about this issue, published in the British Journal of Psychiatry 40 years ago (Reference StengelStengel, 1965), neatly encapsulates the mind-body dualism that was adopted by most practitioners in a more convergent explanation of the origin of pain (Reference SlaterSlater, 1966).

Stengel's work in this area led to a sprouting of interest in Sheffield, where he was the first head of the university's Department of Psychiatry at this time. Three junior psychiatrists in his Department have since become prominent researchers in this area - Harold Merskey, Izzy Pilowsky and Sir Michael Bond. All have contributed massively to the contribution of psychiatric and physical features to the perception of pain, an area into which, sadly, psychiatrists in the UK nowadays rarely venture.

At the same time that Stengel was articulating his views in England, psychiatrists in the USA developed psychological theories to assist in the management of pain in the New World. The established physician and truncated phonemic associate George Engel believed that, although pain may originally develop from an external source, it often becomes a psychological phenomenon (Reference EngelEngel, 1959). He described risk factors for developing chronic pain, including a history of defeat, significant guilt, unsatisfied aggressive impulses and a history of real or imagined loss. Later, Blumer & Heilbronn (Reference Blumer and Heilbronn1982) described a group of patients who developed chronic pain who had a strong work ethic and were preoccupied with their pain. As these individuals later developed many of the vegetative symptoms of depression, these authors unwisely generalised that chronic pain in such people is a manifestation of depression.

EFFECTS OF PAIN ON PERSONALITY

Although Engel (Reference Engel1959) and Blumer & Heilbronn (Reference Blumer and Heilbronn1982) correctly described factors predisposing to the genesis of chronic painful syndromes in a selected group of patients, the generalisations they made dissuaded colleagues working in this field that the biopsychosocial model espoused by these psychiatrists was necessarily relevant (Reference EngelEngel, 1977). Later studies showed that the development of psychiatric illness more usually follows the development of the chronic painful condition, and ‘pain-proneness’ is not demonstrable in most patients (Reference GamsaGamsa, 1990). The reason why most people in pain complain of distressing symptoms is because of the debilitating and demoralising effects of the pain itself. This contention was supported by an intriguing study carried out 20 years ago. At that time the Minnesota Multiphasic Personality Inventory (MMPI) was a widely used tool in the investigation of those with chronic pain. The typical profile of an individual who had developed chronic pain and had the psychological disposition to do so was a component of high scores on the neurotic triad, the depression, hypochondriasis and hysteria sub-scales, of this instrument. This picture was found in a large proportion of a group of patients being assessed for backpain surgery. By chance, a number of the individuals concerned had previously been tested with this instrument in an earlier epidemiological study. In these people it was found that their premorbid profiles were within normal limits, strongly suggesting that the painful condition from which they were suffering was responsible for the apparent change in the personality picture (Reference Hagedorn, Maruta and SwansonHagedorn et al, 1985). Love & Peck (Reference Love and Peck1987) later showed that this particular MMPI profile found in patients with chronic pain did not represent previous personality functioning but was a consequence of disability.

SOMATOFORM DISORDERS

A minority of patients with chronic pain do fulfil the criteria for the diagnosis of a somatoform disorder. In such conditions there is continued presentation of physical symptoms together with persistent requests for medical investigations despite negative findings of organic illness and reassurance by doctors that the symptoms have no physical basis. The diagnosis par excellence of a somatoform disorder is somatisation disorder, where pain is just one of many symptoms exhibited by the (usually) female patient. This diagnosis is not common, ranging from 0.2% of patients referred to a liaison psychiatry service (Reference Smith, Clarke and HandrinosSmith et al, 2000) to 5% of medical patients (Reference Fink, Hansen and OxhojFink et al, 2004). This figure is higher than the previous figure of Smith et al (Reference Smith, Clarke and Handrinos2000) because Fink et al (Reference Fink, Hansen and Oxhoj2004) used ICD-10 criteria. The ICD-10 diagnosis of persistent somatoform pain disorder was 1.5% in this same population (Reference Fink, Hansen and OxhojFink et al, 2004). This low figure is not too surprising, as the latter diagnosis can be made only if the pain described by the patient ‘occurs in association with emotional conflict or psychosocial problems that are sufficient to allow the conclusion that they are the main causative influences’ (World Health Organization, 1992: p. 168). Contrast this with the diagnosis of pain disorder listed in the somatoform disorders section in DSM-IV (American Psychiatric Association, 1994). For this diagnosis to be made, ‘psychological factors are judged to have an important role in the onset, severity, exacerbation, or maintenance of the pain’ (p. 461). Although cases largely due to physical illness are excluded, as also are cases where the pain is ‘better accounted for by a mood, anxiety or psychotic disorder’, more cases with pain and emotional sequelae achieve this level of diagnosis on the DSM-IV schedule than on ICD-10.

The differentiation of the somatoform disorders has been questioned (Reference Wessely, Nimnuan and SharpeWessely et al, 1999). The problem with the diagnosis of somatoform disorders in general and of somatoform pain disorders in particular is the judgement required that the symptoms manifest are due to psychological factors. It is not easy to determine this objectively and most psychiatrists working in the area are aware that physical and psychological factors both contribute significantly to the presentation (Reference MayouMayou, 1991; Reference MerskeyMerskey, 2000). The evidence of psychological causation cannot be assumed from a history of previous risk factors. The reporting of unexplained pain symptoms as due to previously experienced psychological trauma has been found to be an artefact of retrospective self-report rather than a consequence of actual events (Reference Raphael, Widom and LangeRaphael et al, 2001). This being said, there is evidence that some non-organic pains arising in adolescence have a psychogenic basis (Reference Hotopf, Mayou and WadsworthHotopf et al, 1999).

The value of the present classifications of these syndromes has been brought into question because of the imprecise categorisation of such disorders and the fact that many patients fall into the category of undifferentiated somatoform disorder, a watered-down version of somatisation disorder (Reference Bass, Peveler and HouseBass et al, 2001; Reference Sharpe and MayouSharpe & Mayou, 2004). Dimensional assessment of pain on the axes of nociception, evaluation of pain, mood consequences of the pain and pain behaviour (Reference Karoly and JensenKaroly & Jensen, 1987; Reference James and TyrerJames, 1992) may be of greater clinical relevance.

BOOKS ON PSYCHOSOMATIC PAIN

Edward Shorter, the prominent medical historian, has shown how the symptoms of psychosomatic illness have changed over the years. He believes that these symptoms are presented according to the prevailing culture. In the early 1800s, for example, a current concept to explain back pain was spinal irritation, caused by pressure at specific spinal tender spots, leading to nerve and muscle pains. Shorter's contention is that psychosomatic symptoms are selected carefully from a culturally determined symptom pool to give the impression of origin from an underlying organic disease, thus avoiding ridicule (Reference ShorterShorter, 1992). This assumption is supported by the changing terminology of diagnostic labels such as hysteria and neurasthenia.

A recently published book argues that fear of pain explains the high prevalence of psychological distress in patients with chronic pain (Reference Asmundson, Vlaeyen and CrombezAsmundson et al, 2004). There are two schools of thought to explain why a minority of people behaves in this way; these are interrelated. One claims that a catastrophic meaning is placed on the experience of pain because of the fear of injury or re-injury. The other suggests that fear of pain is due to fear of anxiety-related sensations associated with painful episodes. This hypothesis has led to treatment by graded exposure to such situations to enable individuals to learn to manage both anxiety and pain together (Reference Vlaeyen, de Jong and GeilenVlaeyen et al, 2002). For more general reading on psychosomatic disorders, books by Chris Bass (1990) and Peter Manu (2004) are recommended.

As is usually the case with a medical condition that is imperfectly understood and has no established cure, there is a plethora of books for sufferers from pain. One that has received considerable plaudits from patients is The Mindbody Prescription, on treatment for back pain (Reference SarnoSarno, 1998). Dr John Sarno believes that tension is the underlying cause of many back problems. He states ‘Pain serves to smother the emotions so they don't break through to the conscious mind. The brain produces these symptoms as… a distraction to make sure your internal rage does not come out’ (p. ). Although treated with scepticism by his medical colleagues Dr Sarno is clearly appreciated by many pain sufferers in North America. A useful part of the therapy process is educational, in the form of a lecture presentation in which the temporal relationship between emotional feelings and pain is recognised.

THE FUTURE

The specialty of pain has grown considerably over the past 25 years and the influence of the psyche on painful symptoms and vice versa has become much more widely recognised. The difficulty in disentangling the mechanisms involved in this relationship will be clear to those who have read to the end of this piece. Those wishing to obtain more information are recommended to contact the International Association for the Study of Pain (IASP; http://www.iasp-pain.org).

It is in many ways paradoxical that in the UK the vast majority of doctors working in the pain field are anaesthetists, with only a scattering of pharmacologists, neurologists, orthopaedic surgeons and psychiatrists. The value of psychological assistance is more widely recognised. The IASP recommends that all first-class pain clinics should have at least four healthcare professionals on the staff. This is a rare situation in Britain. Until the field of chronic pain is recognised in liaison psychiatry job plans, there is unlikely to be major input from psychiatrists in the UK into chronic painful conditions. If a Faculty of Pain Medicine or similar organisation were to be designated, this might change.

References

American Psychiatric Association (1994) Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders (4th edn) (DSM-IV). Washington, DC: APA.Google Scholar
Asmundson, G. J. G., Vlaeyen, J. W. S. & Crombez, G. (2004) Understanding and Treating Fear of Pain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bass, C. (1990) Somatization: Physical Symptoms and Psychological Illness. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific.Google Scholar
Bass, C., Peveler, R. & House, A. (2001) Somatoform disorders: severe psychiatric illnesses neglected by psychiatrists. British Journal of Psychiatry, 179, 1114.Google Scholar
Blumer, D. & Heilbronn, M. (1982) Chronic pain as a variant of depressive disease. The pain-prone disorder. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 170, 381406.Google Scholar
Breuer, J. & Freud, S. (1957) Studies on Hysteria (trans. Strachey, J.). New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1647) Meditations Touchant la Première Philosophie. Geneva: Athena (http://un2sg4.unige.ch/athena/descartes/desc=med=frame0.html)Google Scholar
Engel, G. (1959) “Psychogenic” pain and the pain-prone patient. American Journal of Medicine, 26, 899918.Google Scholar
Engel, G. (1977) The need for a new medical model: a challenge for biomedical science. Science, 196, 129136.Google Scholar
Fields, H. L. & Price, D. D. (1994) Pain: perceptual properties and neural mechanisms. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind (ed. Guttenplan, S.), pp. 452459. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Fink, P., Hansen, M. S. & Oxhoj, M. L. (2004) The prevalence of somatoform disorders among internal medical inpatients. Journal of Psychosomatic Research, 56, 413418.Google Scholar
Gamsa, A. (1990) Is emotional disturbance a precipitator or a consequence of chronic pain? Pain, 42, 183195.Google Scholar
Hagedorn, S. D., Maruta, T., Swanson, D. W., et al (1985) Premobid MMPI profiles of low back pain patients. Surgical successes versus surgical failures. Clincial Journal of Pain, 1, 177179.Google Scholar
Hotopf, M., Mayou, R., Wadsworth, M., et al (1999) Psychosocial and developmental antecedents of chest pain in young adults. Psychosomatic Medicine, 61, 861867.Google Scholar
James, P. T. (1992) Psychological dimensions of chronic pain. In Psychology, Psychiatry and Chronic Pain (ed. Tyrer, S. P.), pp. 2543. Oxford: Butterworth-Heinemann.Google Scholar
Karoly, P. & Jensen, M. P. (1987) Multimethod Assessment of Chronic Pain. Oxford: Pergamon Press.Google Scholar
Livingston, W. K. (1998) Pain and Suffering. Seattle: IASP Press.Google Scholar
Love, P. W. & Peck, C. L. (1987) The MMPI and psychological factors in chronic low back pain: a review. Pain, 28, 12.Google Scholar
Manu, P. (2004) Psychopathology of Functional Somatic Syndromes: Neurobiology and Illness Behavior in Chronic Fatigue Syndrome, Fibromyalgia, Gulf War Illness, Irritable Bowel Syndrome, and Premenstrual Syndrome. Binghamton, NY: Haworth Press.Google Scholar
Mayou, R. A. (1991) Medically unexplained physical symptoms. BMJ, 303, 534535.Google Scholar
Merskey, H. (1965) The characteristics of persistent pain in psychological illness. Journal of Psychosomatic Research, 9, 29298.Google Scholar
Merskey, H. (2000) Beware of somatization. European Journal of Pain, 4, 34.Google Scholar
Merskey, H., Lau, C. L., Russell, E. S., et al (1987) Screening for psychiatric morbidity. The pattern of psychological illness and premorbid characteristics in four chronic pain populations. Pain, 30, 458.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Raphael, K. G., Widom, C. S. & Lange, G. (2001) Childhood victimization and pain in adulthood: a prospective investigation. Pain, 92, 283293.Google Scholar
Sarno, J. E. (1998) The Mindbody Prescription: Healing the Body, Healing the Pain. New York: Warner Books.Google Scholar
Sharpe, M. & Mayou, R. (2004) Somatoform disorders: a help or hindrance to good patient care? British Journal of Psychiatry, 184, 465467.Google Scholar
Shorter, E. (1992) From Paralysis to Fatigue: A History of Psychosomatic Illness in the Modern Era. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Slater, E. (1966) Pain and the psychiatrist (letter). British Journal of Psychiatry, 112, 329–33.Google Scholar
Smith, G. C., Clarke, D. M., Handrinos, D., et al (2000) Consultation-liaison psychiatrists’ management of somatoform disorders. Psychosomatics, 41, 48489.Google Scholar
Stengel, E. (1965) Pain and the psychiatrist. British Journal of Psychiatry, 111, 795802.Google Scholar
Tyrer, S. P., Capon, N., Peterson, D. N., et al (1989) The detection of psychiatric illness and psychological handicaps in a British pain clinic population. Pain, 36, 6374.Google Scholar
Vlaeyen, J. W., de Jong, J., Geilen, M., et al (2002) The treatment of fear of movement/(re)injury in chronic low back pain: further evidence on the effectiveness of exposure in vivo . Clinical Journal of Pain, 18, 2526.Google Scholar
Wessely, S., Nimnuan, C. & Sharpe, M. (1999) Functional somatic syndromes: one or many? Lancet, 354, 936939.Google Scholar
World Health Organization (1992) The ICD-10 Classification of Mental and Behavioural Disorders. Geneva: WHO.Google Scholar
Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.