Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-nwzlb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T02:26:43.605Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Oxford Handbook of the Self Oxford Handbooks in Philosophy. Edited by Shaun Gallagher. Oxford University Press. 2011. £85.00 (hb). 768pp. ISBN: 9780199548019

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

Julian C. Hughes*
Affiliation:
Old Age Psychiatry and Honorary Professor of Philosophy of Ageing, North Tyneside General Hospital, Rake Lane, North Shields, NE29 8NH, UK. Email: julian.hughes@newcastle.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Book reviews
Copyright
Copyright © Royal College of Psychiatrists, 2011 

I could not help recalling Francis Bacon while reading this book: ‘Read not to contradict and confute, nor to believe and take for granted, nor to find talk and discourse, but to weigh and consider’. It would, after all, be surprising if in 31 chapters on the topic of ‘the self’ there were nothing to try to ‘contradict and confute’. Equally, in a beautifully produced book written by a host of intellectual luminaries, I was often inclined ‘to believe and take for granted’.

It is a book written by philosophers and psychologists. The whole series of Oxford Handbooks is an impressive (and expanding) academic achievement. They are mainly philosophical, but much in this volume would be of interest to psychiatrists. Although the discussion is focused on issues around and conceptions of the self, a variety of psychopathologies make an appearance, for example derealisation, depersonalisation and phantom limb phenomena. The findings of developmental psychology are used to elucidate our sense of self. Neuroimaging in connection with self-recognition is discussed and several chapters probe the relationship of neuroscience to philosophy. The intellectual challenges in this area are brought out by the editor in his introduction: ‘Depending on the precise nature of the questions being asked, there seems to be overwhelming evidence that the self is both everywhere and nowhere in the brain’ (p. 4). There are chapters on multiple personality disorder, autism, anorexia and schizophrenia.

The most exciting sections, for me anyway, were those that showed how philosophy might change or clarify clinical practice. It seems invidious to name any particular chapter in a book full of such expertise, but that by Parnas and Sass on self-consciousness in schizophrenia was masterful. Their claim is that schizophrenia should be associated with disorders that ‘affect the articulation and functioning’ of the ‘minimal or core self’ (p. 532). They say: ‘a phenomenological approach, in particular one centred on disorders of self-experience, offers the possibility of capturing the elusive yet distinctive, unifying features of the schizophrenic disorders’ (p. 542). On this basis they bemoan the lack of intimate long-term acquaintance in contemporary psychiatric practice, which might mitigate some of the disturbance in the person’s sense of subjectivity.

The richness in this volume cannot be captured by a brief review. But, then, the richness of the concept of self cannot be pinned down by any single approach. Those who tend to reductionism fail to convey a really convincing sense of the lived self, which is – as many of these authors suggest – both embodied and embedded (p. 619) or situated (p. 717). In this regard the philosopher Edmund Husserl was quoted twice (pp. 328 and 527) as describing ‘a transcendence in the immanence’. So, although (in postmodern mode) we may wish to eschew any notion of a Platonic transcendent world (p. 696), nonetheless we may yet wish to hang on to a sense of other, of something beyond the material, captured by the concept of ‘self’ but played out or revealed through our bodily goings on in the context of the human world. This is, after all, at the heart of psychiatry: a concern for the psyche as demonstrated bodily in specific cultural, historical and social contexts.

There is, thus, plenty for the psychiatrist to ‘weigh and consider’ in this volume. But if I may stoop to one criticism, there is almost nothing (a few passing references) to do with dementia. And I would have thought that the reality of dementia should tell us a lot about the self. As Hermans says, ‘The self can only be properly understood when intersubjectivity and sociality are considered as intrinsic to its embodiment in space and time’ (p. 654). This has implications for our understanding of people with dementia; but, then, it has implications for all of us.

Submit a response

eLetters

No eLetters have been published for this article.